53 pages • 1 hour read
Roderick NashA modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more.
Nash begins this chapter by citing a passage written by Robert Wernick, a staunch critic of the preservation movement. Using derisive language, Wernick and those like him tended to revert the wilderness question back to its original binary form in which its relationship with civilization was adversarial: Wilderness was the enemy both in the physical world and within the human psyche. In response to criticisms like these, preservationists struggled to offer a coherent philosophy that deconstructed this binary. For critics of preservation, the issue often came down to a simple premise, as Eric Hoffer articulated: “The globe […] should be man’s and not nature’s” (241). In addition, Nash discusses the views of Rene Dubos, a French microbiologist, who saw the cultivation of wilderness as a natural act of human progress. Unlike Wernick and others, Dubos was not derisive toward preservationists. He understood their belief structures but felt that the natural course of human history should unfold unencumbered by artificial constraints. Eric Julber shared this thinking. Unlike Wernick, he valued natural beauty but argued that wilderness preservation was the concern of a small minority. He believed that making the beauty of nature more accessible for the largest number of people was a more beneficial strategy than keeping wilderness areas accessible for only those who had the physical and financial means.
Preservationists like Benton McKaye and Sigurd Olsen meditated on the interdependence of human civilization and wilderness. Olsen particularly understood that without a civilization to return to, his wilderness experiences would lose value. John P. Milton, another preservationist, further explored the fusion of civilization and wilderness in American life and clarified the concept that Olsen expressed: “The very concepts of civilization and wilderness require each other to have real meaning” (246). These notable figures and others, including poet Gary Snyder, attempted to reconcile and balance the human need for society with the need for wilderness to tap into a different aspect of one’s being.
The evolution of this balanced approach climaxed in what Nash refers to as “[a] simple scarcity theory of value, coupled with the shrinking size of the American wilderness relative to American civilization” (248). Nash touches on a growing cultural awareness of the importance of wilderness, especially in the 1960s. He examines the counterculture movement’s embrace of wilderness in protesting materialism. Gradually, the preservation movement morphed into an awareness that humankind was perhaps vulnerable. No longer was human civilization certain to survive an everlasting impulse to dominate its environment. The preservation movement, therefore, evolved into the environmentalist movement. The last part of this chapter centers on a discussion of the early environmentalist movement and the associated evolution of thought. Leading figures of the early movement convincingly advocated for the necessity of wilderness preservation as crucial to human health in a way that others before them were unable to do. The chapter concludes by exploring the various philosophies of those who view human civilization and wilderness as interconnected, not adversarial.
Nash begins this chapter by mentioning the landmark 1980 passage of the Alaska National Interest Lands Conservation Act, the “greatest single act of wilderness preservation in world history” (272). He then lays out a rationale for why Alaska is different from traditional cultural perceptions of the frontier. Residents typically viewed protecting the Alaskan environment as intrusive and unnecessary. The environment, specifically the climate and the short growing season, is the first rationale for why Alaska is not like the western frontier of the 1800s. Nash posits technology as another rationale. The pace of technology by the 1950s was so far ahead of the original frontier American West that conquering the land could have occurred much more quickly. The third explanation is the presence of Indigenous populations. The conquest of the western frontier displaced and killed Indigenous populations, whereas Alaskan frontier efforts did not subject the Indigenous population to such treatment to the same degree. In the haste to protect the Alaskan wilderness, many of the elite in the lower 48 states simply forgot the place of Indigenous populations in the overall scheme of things. The Lands Conservation Act allowed for the concurrent preservation of land and the economic motivations of Indigenous populations.
Nash chronicles some prominent figures who visited Alaska, including John Muir, Jack London, and Robert Marshall. The timing of Alaskan exploration is important in that it occurred after the settling of the original American frontier. The early preservation movement, led by Muir, influenced popular thinking just enough that expansion into and development of Alaska involved far more respect for the land and the Indigenous people who lived there. After Alaska received statehood in 1959, economic interests and the preservation movement once again came into direct opposition over the construction of a dam, in this case the Rampart Dam on the Yukon River. Nash outlines the differing views of the interested parties—and like the other dam projects he mentions in the book, the issue centered on the same dilemma: whether the dam’s potential economic benefit was worth sacrificing a pristine wilderness. Eventually, in 1967, the Department of the Interior dropped the dam proposal. Nash discusses how pop culture influenced the dropped legislation and references many books, writers, and films that eventually turned Alaska into a tourist hot spot. Nash concludes the chapter by discussing a former governor, Jay Hammond, who was something of a contradiction. A preservationist and an avid outdoors enthusiast, he understood the need to protect the Alaskan wilderness—but he also realized that development could better the lives of Alaskan citizens economically. Robert Weeden, a biologist at the University of Alaska, advised Hammond, advocating a balanced approach to land management that recognized the need to keep Alaska pristine while working the wilderness in a way that provided economic benefit to the population.
With the successes of the preservation movement, a new problem emerged. This chapter explores how in the last two to three decades of the 20th century, the wilderness became increasingly crowded: “Having made extraordinary gains in the public’s estimation in the last century, wilderness could well be loved to death in the next” (316). Achieving the goal of building appreciation for wilderness resulted in unintended consequences. Nash cites data on recreational land usage over decades, and the increase in visitors to popular wilderness areas was dramatic. He posits an explanation for the boom in wilderness recreation, claiming that four revolutions caused the spike: intellectual, equipment, transportation, and information. The three latter revolutions could be traced to technological improvements that gave the average person easier access to wilderness areas. The increasing popularity of wilderness recreation created an urgent need to manage it so that visitors did not destroy the wilderness—something that early preservationists did not anticipate.
As preservationists began to see the need to control the number of visitors to wilderness areas, they first looked to the policies that guided sheep herders, specifically “carrying capacity,” which limited how many sheep could graze in an area. Carrying capacity of humans meant “the ability of an environment to absorb human influence and still retain its wildness” (323). In moving on from discussing this early awareness, Nash documents the evolution of policies to control the visitor volume and the philosophical justification for it. Once again, debates arose that Nash categorizes as biocentrism versus anthropocentrism, the central issue being the question of whom wilderness is truly for: nature or humans. Nash examines the debate in detail and cites visitor attendance to the Grand Canyon as a case study. In the late 1960s and into the 1970s, the Grand Canyon’s popularity grew to the point that it threatened the canyon’s wilderness health and forced the National Park Service to act. One of its first steps was to ban motorized craft on the Colorado River. Naturally, this created controversy: Many people, including commercial outfitters, depended on motorized craft—and felt entitled to use them. Nash concludes the chapter by returning to its main idea: the paradox of wilderness management.
The chapter begins by comparing the European tourist (such as George Gore of England) in the 1850s American West with the American tourist (such as Theodore Roosevelt) in early 1900s Africa. The expansion into the American frontier in 1890 marks the dividing line between eras in which Americans and tourists could no longer experience the original frontier as they perceived of it; therefore, they had to seek other places on the globe to pursue some semblance of it. This comparison frames Nash’s central idea in this chapter: the importation/exportation of nature. He claims that the more civilized a nation, the more it imports nature, and the less civilized a nation, the more it exports nature. In exploring this phenomenon, Nash provides anecdotes and data, including a graph, to substantiate his claim.
Nash provides an historical account of how the American West before 1890 was an exporter of nature to Europeans. A tension arose between these European tourists, who were typically wealthy and who considered themselves “sportsmen,” and American pioneers, whose utilitarian motives viewed wilderness as something to be conquered. According to Nash, a significant part of the motivation for protecting Yellowstone was the prospect of economic gains in the form of tourism. The more money that European tourists spent on visiting Yellowstone, the more they believed that they should have some influence on its protection. Their approach was exclusionary in that they wanted Yellowstone protected for their own concerns and did not consider the larger rationale for wilderness protection that others like John Muir advocated.
Through the 1850s and beyond, the US gradually changed from exporting to importing wilderness. Nash cites the decline of the buffalo as evidence of the US pivot from exporter to importer. As the buffalo population dwindled to near extinction, Americans such as Theodore Roosevelt sought other areas on the globe to hunt big game. Because of its abundance of big game, Africa became a popular destination for wealthy Americans, and the more they traveled there as tourists, the more it became an importer of wilderness rather than an exporter. As importers of nature, therefore, the US and European countries sought to protect and preserve the wilderness, realizing its intrinsic value. So-called civilized societies imposed their preservationism to suit their own ends despite any objections of the Indigenous populations. Albert National Park in the Belgian Congo is one example. Nash discusses how the park came to be and what influenced its inception. After World War II, a global wilderness protection movement gained momentum, and the United Nations took a more prominent role in it. Nash concludes the chapter by discussing the UNESCO World Heritage Site program, which grew out of this movement.
In the Epilogue, Nash speaks for himself in the first-person voice, which is a stark departure from the rest of the book. He wrote this Epilogue some 50 years after the book’s original (1967) publication. Nash uses it to update his work and make it more pertinent for current readers. In addition, he speculates on the future of wilderness for humanity. Nash proposes two ways to view the future of wilderness: One is a vision in which humanity has created a wasteland and essentially destroyed the natural world; the other is one in which humans have subdued nature to the point that humans control all elements of it. Although the latter vision, which Nash calls this the “garden scenario,” seems benign, Nash contends that it is not; instead, the ends are the same in both scenarios because they completely subjugate nature to humanity.
Nash then proposes a third scenario that is not on the garden/wasteland spectrum. This concept, which he calls “island civilization,” essentially inverts how things stand in modern times. Rather than have small islands of wilderness amid vast tracts of civilization, Nash suggests that humanity should strive to flip this so that pockets of civilization exist amid large swaths of wilderness. He feels that increasing technological abilities can help make this happen. For this inversion to become a reality, Nash points out that humanity must fundamentally change from almost always using technology to subdue wilderness areas for its own ends. Importantly, he emphasizes that technology itself is “neutral” and that ethical judgment results from how humans use technology.
Island civilization will involve restraint and a willingness to stand down. Nash creatively visualizes what this “new world” could look like. He readily admits that he does not have all the answers as to how his idea might come to fruition, but he believes that it could happen if humanity develops the right mindset about existing side-by-side with nature. In Nash’s view, this trend has already begun, as he demonstrates throughout the book. The ways that our views on wilderness have evolved and continue to evolve make ideas like his feasible.
The beginning of Chapter 13 and the derisive comments of Robert Wernick highlight the growing divide between the utilitarian and the preservationist. Nash quotes Wernick as saying, “they affect old rumpled clothes, unshaved jaws, salty language; they spit and sweat and boast of their friendship with aborigines” (248). This quote exemplifies the ad hominem fallacy, as it attacks the caricatured version of a preservationist rather than responding to the argument that preservationists were making. It also implies that to support the preservationist cause, a person must also support the uncivilized and uncouth. Also implicit in Wernick’s quote is classism, as it brings to the surface what constitutes civilized behavior, good manners, and proper etiquette by referencing examples of the opposite. In simple terms, Wernick said that those who wanted to be considered civilized members of society should not affiliate themselves with the likes he portrayed. Such mockery might provoke those with moderate views that recognize the validity of both sides of the argument to reconsider their views.
In response to such caricatures, preservationists began to realize the need for a coherent and unifying philosophy. According to Nash, the primary impetus was a need “for ideas that defend wilderness in general in the way that the philosophy of human freedom underlies the many specific defenses of civil liberty” (238). This strategy suggests an awareness that preservation as a movement needed to abandon its binary position as an opposing force for civilization. Rather than defending wilderness protection from Wernick and others, preservationists attempted to reconcile the civilization/wilderness divide by seeing in humanity a need for both. Benton MacKaye and John P. Milton, borrowing from Thoreau and Emerson, posited ideas suggesting that humanity’s ideal state was the ability to access both civilization and wilderness: “Milton felt that a way of life which alternated between wilderness and civilization was the solution to ambivalence” (246). Seen in this light, the issue did not have to be an either/or proposition; one did not have to choose between wilderness or civilization. In fact, access to both was better for a person’s emotional and mental state. For Milton, wilderness and civilization were not binary antonyms. From this baseline, the philosophy evolved by addressing opposing concerns. According to Nash, the movement began to directly address the perception that preservationists wanted a return to pre-civilization. Howard Zahniser claimed publicly that wilderness advocates “were not recommending a return to cave dwelling on a permanent basis” (247). Instead, Zahniser argued, wilderness allowed people a refuge “to get away from the technology that gives us the illusion of mastering rather than belonging to the environment” (254). Although the idea that we belong to the environment was not entirely novel at the time, it was not an accepted truth either. Statements like Zahniser’s were crucial to moving the debate away from the binary idea of wilderness protection and civilization being locked in an adversarial relationship.
Nash uses the National Interest Lands Conservation Act as a framing device for Chapter 14, which explores Alaska and the perception that at one time it represented a new frontier for the US. For preservationists, many of whom would never venture to Alaska, the way that American culture and government agencies responded to this was that “Alaska represented the nation’s last chance to do things right the first time” (272). On the heels of the conquest of the western frontier and the view of wilderness as an enemy, the reach into Alaska provided an opportunity to learn from past mistakes, notable among them the complete devastation of buffalo herds and consequential, lasting environmental devastation. After discussing the National Interest Lands Conservation Act of 1980, Nash rewinds the tape and provides an historical synopsis of the Alaskan frontier and the debates that inevitably arose as to the use of the wilderness there.
As Alaska gained statehood in 1959, most considered it too big and too rugged for civilization to overcome. Early settlers and residents thought that protecting the Alaskan wilderness was unnecessary because the environment was so brutal that it would be unconquerable: “Wilderness preservation simply did not make much sense to pioneers. They tended to be much more concerned about preserving themselves” (273). This calls to mind similar sentiments that earlier pioneers settling the West expressed about self-preservation in the face of the unknown threats that the wilderness posed. In Alaska, the threat to human life was even more pervasive because of its inhospitable climate. Nash chronicles some of the ways that harsh climates—including the Alaska’s relatively treeless landscape—make living difficult, even for non-human species.
Technological innovation enabled easier access to the Alaskan wilderness and increased the ability to civilize it. When Alaska was granted statehood, technological progress was far ahead of the original frontier days: “What required a decade in the West could be done in a few months in the North” (275). As an example, Nash discusses the bush plane. By the time of the 1980 legislation, many preservationists recognized the looming threat that civilization’s technological advancements posed to wilderness. While opponents still maintained that land protection was unnecessary, a cultural reckoning with the past spurred a new way of thinking: Because wilderness itself is a resource just as much as oil, timber, and water, it must be managed appropriately.
Chapter 15 examines the unintended consequences of the preservation movement’s growth. Nash mentions elsewhere that wealthy, elite members of society—beginning with Thoreau and Emerson—typically generated and maintained the movement. Preservation of wilderness was mostly a classist concern, and the impetus was not generally the betterment of all classes of society. The ability to travel and spend considerable time in the wilderness was then a luxury that required tremendous planning and financial resources. However, by the 1960s and 1970s, this dynamic had changed. Nash calls this a “revolution” and breaks it down into four components: intellectual, equipment, transportation, and information. Essentially, these components opened access to increasingly more people. Gradually, wilderness areas across the US saw tremendous increases in attendance over relatively few years. The sheer volume presented a new problem for the preservation movement, something unforeseen in John Muir’s time: Too many people were going to the woods.
In response, policymakers of the 1970s began to develop land management programs: “Wilderness management rests on the assumption that uncontrolled wilderness recreation is just as much a threat to wilderness qualities as economic development” (320). In essence, the question is what wilderness quality a place retains when thousands of people continuously visiting it. As he does throughout the book, Nash presents two ends of the spectrum and then shows how policies have fluctuated between biocentric and anthropocentric positions. He points to the Grand Canyon as a case study in how wilderness management has fluctuated between these ends. As access to the park became easier, more people flocked to it. Between 1960 and 1970, the park saw an increase of more than 9,000 visitors. It began to lose its wilderness quality and resemble a resort. Policy initiatives, such as “carrying capacity” and the banning of motorized boats, caused controversy that centered on the ongoing dilemma of how humans should use wilderness: “The Grand Canyon allocation controversy raised the deeper question of what kind of use is most appropriate in a federally managed wilderness” (338). Although the early preservationists did not foresee this issue, it remains a complicated question to answer, as Nash points out in the book’s Prologue.
The purpose of Chapter 16 is twofold. First, Nash attempts to define wilderness in economic terms. The import/export binary explains how economies around the world use wilderness as a commodity. He provides historical context as it applies to America and traces how the US transformed from an exporter to an importer of wilderness. Second, Nash illustrates the relationship between a society’s economic growth and the inevitably of it becoming an importer of wilderness. Nash points out that for the most part, historically and in modern times, the importing of wilderness was generally conducted by those who could afford it: “A social profile of their ranks would reveal an inordinately high proportion of scientists, writers, artists—people of quality and the affluence to pay for it” (343). This comment recalls notable figures, such as Thoreau and Robert Marshall, who themselves were of affluent backgrounds. Nash does not venture to study of the inequality of wilderness access across the ages; instead, he shows how the willingness of affluent people to spend money on a wilderness experience is an economic driver for nations where a true wilderness experience is available.
The desire among the elite of the early 1900s to hunt big game—a practice that many today would consider unethical—had a long-term positive impact on preservation. Nash does not gloss over the horrific devastation of North America’s buffalo herds but highlights it as a pivotal moment in the pursuit of better worldwide wildlife protection initiatives. Prominent people, such as Theodore Roosevelt, began to realize that big game was not a limitless resource and that unregulated hunting could lead to extinction. In some ways, the expansion into the American frontier provides valuable lessons on what not to do in terms of how humankind interacts with wild places. Other parts of the world could learn from where America went wrong in its own frontier. The importation of wilderness therefore led to growth in urgent preservation initiatives around the world. Of course, as in the past, tensions arose between Indigenous populations and outsiders who sought to impose their own brand of wilderness values. This calls into question many aspects of colonialism. However, in a world where wholesale subjugation of wilderness by civilization seemed certain, recognition by other countries of their own role in the preservation movement had a positive effect.
Nash wrote the Epilogue some 50 years after book’s original publication, and it has an important function. First, it adds relevance to the book’s content and primary ideas. With the Epilogue, the book seems far less dated. While the historical discussions end around 1980, the Epilogue allows current readers to realize that the cultural significance of the book’s central claims have only grown. Second, Nash changes his point of view in the Epilogue. Rather than continuing in the objective, third-person voice that he uses for the rest of the book, Nash asserts his own views through the first-person voice, which enables him to shift from a fact-based analysis of history to a speculative, theoretical discussion in which he shares his own visions for the future. Interestingly, Nash does not editorialize much on the historical evolution and ethics of humanity’s relationship with wilderness. He does not pass judgment or indict civilization’s need for progress. Instead, he assumes that the human need for progress will, by necessity, continue. This concession is important, as it endows his island civilization scenario with realism. The scenario is far less idealistic than if he had, for instance, called for a halt to progress and pleaded for a return to Primitivism.
Nash’s tone in the Epilogue is not alarmist, nor does it serve as a doomsday warning. It does not suggest that we must do something or else. If anything, it offers an optimistic view that attempts to reframe the argument out of its binary structure. The future of humanity’s relationship to wilderness does not have to be an either/or proposition; it need not be either a wasteland or a controlled paradise, both of which would depend on utter subjugation of nature to the will of humankind. His idea is creative. It shows how imagination can play a role in what the future should look like, and its premise is not complex. Today’s maps show areas bounded areas, usually in a shade of green, to indicate wilderness, parks, or preserves, which take up little space on a map. Nash’s idea asks us to imagine the map drawn the same way but inverted so that most of it is green and the civilized areas are bounded. By positing a broad idea outside the binary, Nash shows one way of securing a better future for humanity and wilderness.