logo

39 pages 1 hour read

Plato

Theaetetus

Nonfiction | Book | Adult

A modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more.

Chapters 21-28Chapter Summaries & Analyses

Chapter 21 Summary: “Perception Scrutinized”

Theaetetus reminds Socrates and Theodorus that they neglected to examine the opposite of the theory that everything changes, which they agreed to do in chapter 19. This is the theory “that the universe is one and at rest” (66), an idea that was originally developed by the philosopher Parmenides. However, Socrates argues that discussing this theory would be too time consuming and too much of a diversion from the topic of knowledge.

Chapter 22 Summary: “The Role of the Mind”

Returning to the question of knowledge, Socrates says that we perceive through the various sense organs. Everything gained though these senses converges on, and is united in, the “mind” (69). The mind then organizes and gives meaning to various sensory stimuli to form a coherent perception. In this way, the mind can consider things given to it by the body—yet it can also consider things by itself. It can form judgments about the “being” of something. This means it can use contrast and calculation to establish the nature of an object in terms of its likeness and difference to other objects, as well as its usefulness and aesthetic qualities. Further, it is the understanding of an object’s “being,” or nature, that constitutes knowledge.

Chapter 23 Summary: “Knowledge Is Perception Refuted”

Socrates draws his final conclusion about Protagoras’s theory. Since understanding the being of a phenomenon constitutes knowledge, knowledge cannot consist in perception. This is because perception does not give access to such being. Instead, any investigation into the meaning of knowledge must proceed by looking at “what the mind is doing when it’s busying itself, by itself, about the things which are” (71). In short, the enquiry into knowledge must look at the mind and reason if it wishes to find the truth. Theaetetus offers a preliminary point of orientation for such an enquiry by suggesting that “true judgment is knowledge” (72).

Chapter 24 Summary: “Paradoxes of False Judgment”

Examining Theaetetus’s suggestion that knowledge is true judgment, Socrates focuses on the distinction between true and false judgment, upon which this idea relies. He argues that false judgment cannot mean having a judgment about things that do not exist. This is because any sort of judgment must involve the invocation of a phenomenon that at the very least exists in the mind. For example, the idea of a cyclops exists as an idea in the mind of one who thinks about it. Thus, Socrates concludes, false judgment must mean something other than imagining things that do not exist.

Chapter 25 Summary: “Other-Judging”

Socrates attempts to find a solution to the problem of false judgments raised in Chapter 24. He puts forth the idea that false judgment might reside not in imagining something but in thinking something to be other than it is. Thinking is here understood as the mind’s internal dialogue with itself. For example, we might think to ourselves “X is beautiful” when it is in fact ugly. However, Socrates finds that this idea still falls prey to the same problems that face identifying false judgment with imagining something.

Chapter 26 Summary: “The Mind as a Wax Tablet”

We might understand false judgment on the basis of accurate and inaccurate memory. Socrates uses the metaphor of a wax tablet to demonstrate this. When we perceive something, an impression of that thing is imprinted on our mind and memory, as an object leaves an impression on wax. However, false judgment occurs when this imprint from an initial perception is imperfect. It may then happen that this initial imprint does not correspond to a subsequent perception of the same thing. Consider, for example, the case of a person we know but have not seen in years. As our memory of them is imperfect, we may incorrectly judge a different but similar person to be them, or we may fail to recognize them when they are there. This is how false judgment occurs.

Moreover, Socrates argues that this is possible because different people have varying qualities of “wax” for their minds. Some have thick, consistent, and pure wax, and therefore can learn and remember accurately. Others have wax that is impure or excessively fluid or hard, and are thus more prone to poor memory and false judgment.

Chapter 27 Summary: “Criticism of the Wax Tablet Model”

Socrates identifies a problem with the wax tablet analogy as a means of resolving the problem of false judgments. Namely, it only applies to the relationship between perception and thought, and not the operations of thought itself. For instance, false judgment still presents a problem in the case of reflection on numbers. It seems impossible to judge four to be five, even at some future point, once we know what these numbers mean. As such, Socrates tries a different tack. He hopes to make progress by “being prepared to say what knowledge is like” (87). In other words, he hopes to discover a more productive route in his quest for a definition of knowledge by looking at the way we know something.

Chapter 28 Summary: “The Mind as an Aviary”

To examine the way we know things, Socrates uses the metaphor of the mind as an aviary and draws a distinction between “having” and “possessing” (88). As he argues, we can possess something without having it at any given moment. For example, you may own a coat but not have it in your possession right now. Imagining pieces of knowledge in the mind to be like birds in aviary, we may have caught a bird, or learned a piece of knowledge, but we do not have it in our hand, or at the forefront of our mind. To “have” the piece of knowledge we must therefore try and catch, or recollect, it from among other pieces of knowledge. With this idea, Socrates believes he has resolved the problem of false judgment. This is because it can still be said that it is impossible to not possess what one possesses, or to not know what one knows. However, when one tries to grasp a piece of knowledge one possesses, one may fail to do so at a given moment, or may misidentify something we have taken hold off. For example, you may wrongly attribute a certain quote to Heraclitus that was in fact said by Parmenides. Therein lies false judgment.

Chapters 21-28 Analysis

With Chapters 21-23, Socrates believes he has finally refuted Protagoras’s theory of knowledge. His reasoning is revealed in the passage below. As he says, some things can be perceived by “men and animals” from birth:

namely all the things which direct experiences to the mind by means of the body. But as for calculations about those things, with respect to being and usefulness, they’re acquired […] by means of a great deal of troublesome education (70).

Socrates’s argument depends upon a certain dualism. On one hand, the body merely relays sensations to the mind in a mechanistic and un-developing way. On the other hand, the mind is uniquely, by itself, able to organize and assess these perceptions, and its abilities to do so expand and develop over time, as a person becomes more educated. Thus, Socrates concludes, “knowledge is located, not in our experiences, but in our reasoning about those things we mentioned” (71).

Yet, his claim and refutation is perhaps not as definitive as he would like to believe. Certainly, one could raise doubts about aspects of the argument. One problem is his idea that perception cannot count as knowledge since it does not develop, unlike reasoning. This assertion appears to rest on an overly simplistic view of perception. An advocate of Protagoras could well say that we perceive in new or deeper ways as we become more educated. Indeed, they could also say that we perceive more clearly or profoundly as we start to examine our own perceptions. For example, one of the skills of a great painter or writer is not merely an ability to represent what they see in a more sophisticated way than others but an ability to see people, places, and scenes in a different and more penetrating way. Relatedly, this deeper seeing is partly gained from studying great works of art and literature in the first place.

Further, it is not clear why reasoning and perception must be so strictly separated. To think about something, it is not necessary for the mind to be “busying itself, by itself” (71), sealed off from perception. Rather, degrees of thought and reflection can coexist in a more fluid and intertwined relationship with perceiving. For example, when you talk with a friend, you are neither wholly unthinking nor thinking. When your friend talks, you are focused on what they are saying. You are not “lost in thought” or calculating how much you will need to pay. But this attention is not a mindless or passive absorption, free from thought. Your attention is nonreflective but thoughtful. It involves considering and “feeling” the situation, and the meaning of your friend’s words, in a more intuitive and responsive way, one that would be impossible for a child.

It seems, then, that the only cases where knowledge is wholly free from perception is with pure a priori reasoning about entirely abstract concepts, like numbers, logical symbols, or atomized units of language. And, as Immanuel Kant highlighted, the extent to which such analytic truths count as knowledge is contested. For example, do the statements “2+2=4” or “all bachelors are single” reflect knowledge about the world or merely reiterations of the meaning of the concepts “4” and “bachelor”? Nevertheless, the knowledge is perception theory has been severely questioned. Even if an absolute refutation, especially via this last argument, is not forthcoming, Socrates has marshalled enough arguments to render Protagoras’s theory implausible.

As such, he moves on to the theory that knowledge is true judgment. Given that, for Socrates, knowledge must concern the operations of the mind, and not perception, this makes sense. Thus, a statement such as “Socrates is wise” would be an example of knowledge. However, for there to be a true statement, there must also be the possibility of false judgments. Otherwise, all judgments of whatever kind would be true. And this presents the problem or paradox of false judgment. As Socrates says, “if someone makes a judgment, he has in his judgment either one of the things he knows or one of the things he doesn’t know” (73). If he knows something, such as Socrates, how can he make a false judgment about that thing? It seems impossible that he could know that thing and truly make it the subject of a judgment, while also making a false statement about it, such as “Socrates is unwise.” Socrates tries to resolve this difficulty by appealing to different models of the mind. The first is the wax tablet model; the second is the idea of the mind as an aviary. While both reveal interesting things about memory and the difference between implicit and expressed knowledge, and hence what it means to know, it remains to be seen whether either can overcome the problem of false judgment.

blurred text
blurred text
blurred text
blurred text