logo

48 pages 1 hour read

Kōbō Abe

The Woman in the Dunes

Fiction | Novel | Adult | Published in 1962

A modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more.

Themes

Futility Versus Purpose

The concept of futility gets at the heart of many key elements of existentialism, which emphasizes the importance of human freedom and individual experience over objective meaning or knowledge. If something is futile, it is pointless and has no meaning, and existential philosophers debate the very existence of meaning:

Does life have meaning? If so, what gives it meaning? Is purpose something constructed of human will to imbue life with a false sense of meaning? The man, too, wrestles with these ideas, both in the abstract and the concrete.

The idea of shoveling sand night after night just to maintain a difficult and joyless existence initially strikes the man as futile. He understands the impressive, collective power of sand despite each grain’s tiny size, so the effort the villagers make in order to protect their village from sand is preposterous to him. The work is ongoing and endless, and the village is decrepit, so the futility overwhelms him initially. As he says to the woman, “[Y]ou exist only for the purpose of clearing away the sand” (39)—a purpose the man deems neither meaningful nor respectable. In his mind, some purposes have more merit than others. He compares the woman’s efforts, and those of the villagers, to save their home to an anecdote about a mangy mongrel he once had. When he cut the dog’s hair, it howled, grabbed some of the hair, and ran off with it, which he believes demonstrates that, just as the villager’s efforts are pointless, “there’s no sense in such futile concern over a tuft of hair” (66).

The man’s eventual resignation to life in the sand dune, however, is not merely a defeat of his efforts to escape but a growing awareness of and acquiescence to the futility of life. His scientific pursuits, in fact, are “simply ways to escape, however temporarily, from his obligations and the inactivity of his life” (40). He comes to see his hobbies as attempts to dampen his awareness of this futility. Recalling a conversation with Möbius man, he realizes that he had had these questions about existence before coming to the sand village: “I have considerable doubt about a system of education that imputes meaning to life […] an illusory education that makes one believe that something is when it really isn’t” (98). Likewise, when the man contemplates how people go on vacation and force themselves to feel like they are having fun, he recognizes the futility and lack of meaning in life.

The man's feeling that the outside world is just as futile or pointless as the sand dunes is reiterated after he reads the newspaper and decides it is a “tower of illusion, all of it, made of illusory bricks and full of holes. […] everyday life [is] exactly like the headlines. And so everybody, knowing the meaninglessness of existence, sets the center of his compass at his own home” (94). The man begins to develop an understanding about why the sand removal is so important to the villagers as to become the centerpiece of their existence. Their complacency with the situation is, in a sense, their freedom. Their purpose, though repetitious, creates a rhythm for life, and they need not want more than that.

By the end of the novel, the man asserts, “Work seem[s] something fundamental for man, something which enable[s] him to endure the aimless flight of time” (158). He has given in to the futility, and it has become his purpose.

Freedom and Imprisonment

The man’s character arc and experiences in the sand pit provide a reflection on what it means to be free and an interrogation of socially constructed notions of respectability. The story begins with a literal example of imprisonment: the man’s entrapment in the sand dune. He is outraged that the villagers would trap him this way, asking, “[Is] it permissible to snare, exactly like a mouse or an insect, a man who had his certificate of medical insurance, someone who had paid his taxes, who was employed, and whose family records were in order?” (51). The man defines the injustice of his imprisonment in terms of social bureaucracy and respectability. He believes he’s entitled to freedom because of his status as a respectable member of a civilized society. He cites his employment and his ability to pay taxes as reasons he is deserving of freedom, or at least not deserving of imprisonment. The idea that a person merits freedom as a basic human right simply by existing doesn’t initially enter into his equation.

In his interactions with the woman, the man sees a different way of relating to existence. At first, he is “angry at the things that [bind] the woman…and at the woman who let[s] herself be bound” because he is projecting his own insecurities of weakness and powerlessness onto her (39-40). He admonishes her to “’stop being treated like a slave,” claiming that “nobody has the right to keep [her] shut up here” (60). Yet the woman evinces no desire to leave—not just the community, but her own sand pit. She says she has no interest in going for a walk because she used to have to walk all the time and it tired her. Since the story is set in post-war Japan, though she doesn’t say it, her walking may allude to migrations during the war. The man recalls “when everything was in ruins some ten years ago, everybody desperately wanted not to have to walk” and wonders now if they are “glutted with this freedom from walking?” (89-90). By the end of the novel, the man fully shifts his perspective and proves willing to give up any perceived respectability to achieve it. When the old man tells him he can come up for a bit if he lets them watch him have sex with the woman, the man immediately assaults her. He thinks about “what he could get as a prize…ground on which he could walk where he wished” (230). He fails to acknowledge that to claim this prize, he must violate the woman’s freedom and basic human right to body autonomy.

Even as the man gradually accepts his imprisonment, he still feels yearnings for freedom. In part, this desire stems from knowing that not all the people in the community have to live in holes—everyone’s plight is not equally grim. When he is trying to run away, he notices that “just to protect this pitiful bit of geography, more than ten households on the sea side [have] had to submit to a life of slavery” (176). The injustice of that inequality chafes him, exacerbated by the villagers’ constant surveillance—the knowledge that someone with binoculars is watching the people in the sand pits. He muses, “More than iron doors, more than walls, it is the tiny peephole that really makes the prisoner feel locked in” (146). The invasion of privacy reinforces the idea of imprisonment.

The lack of freedom makes the man feel more like an animal than a human, emphasizing the extent to which he defines his own worth via conventions of social respectability, claiming that “even a dog’ll go mad if you keep it shut up in a cage” (89). When he realizes that the villagers will simply withhold water when he threatens to keep the woman in bondage and stop all work, he reiterates the comparison, saying he feels “like an animal who finally sees that the crack in the fence it was trying to escape through is in reality merely the entrance to its cage—like a fish who at last realizes, after bumping its nose numberless times, that the glass of the goldfish bowl is a wall” (123). In his attempt to reassert a sense of his own power (and by extension, his worth), he instinctually assaults the woman, holding her hostage to bargain for his release—something he’s able to justify only by implicitly defining his own worth (as a tax-paying, insurance-holding, male member of civilization) as inherently higher than hers.

Even later, after his will has been broken, there is still a part of the man that yearns for physical freedom. He and the woman discuss getting a plant or small tree. When he imagines it, he sees “clusters of leaves, twisting and fluttering, trying in vain to escape from their branch” (225), and he begins to weep. Freedom of that sort, he accepts, is no longer possible. However, he discovers a new version of freedom when his crow trap turns out to be an effective water trap. Having his own source of water means that he is less dependent on the capricious whims of the villagers. He is “still in the hole, but it seem[s] as if he [is] already outside” (235). The man discovers that having leverage does not require that one use it; that, too, is a type of freedom—the ability to decide for oneself when or if to act. In the end, when presented with the means of escape, the man chooses not to, with the thought that “there [is] no particular need to hurry about escaping” (239). He is exercising the little bit of freedom his new mentality allows, the freedom to do nothing.

Stability Versus Movement

Abe employs irony early in his novel by highlighting the man’s fascination with sand. He admires it for its “ceaseless movement” evoking a sense of freedom (14), yet it becomes the very thing that eventually imprisons him, removing his own freedom of movement. The man contrasts the sand’s constant motion with the “dreary way human beings [cling] together year in year out,” questioning whether “a stationary condition [is] absolutely indispensable for existence? Didn’t unpleasant competition arise precisely because one tried to cling to a fixed position?” (14-15). After his imprisonment, the man envies the sand’s ability to move “about free and unrestricted” (27), a freedom denied to him in the dunes. His attempts to use the sand itself to escape and reclaim the freedom it represents to him prove futile precisely because of its properties of motion.

Just as the sand is an almost insurmountable impediment for him to overcome, so too is it a force that subdues any stationary thing. The man thinks about the “cities of antiquity, whose immobility no one doubted…Yet, after all, they too were unable to resist the law of the flowing 1/8-mm. sands” (41). In the scientific query of an irresistible force meeting an immoveable object, the sand, in the man’s mind, always wins out, given enough time. His appreciation of its power leads to his identification with it, even fleetingly as he considers “the effect of the flowing sands, he [is] seized from time to time by hallucinations in which he himself began to move with the flow” (15). The man’s obsession with the sand’s motion and power mirrors Abe’s own well-documented dislike of stability. The man scorns the villagers for clinging to their life in the sad, little village, even going so far as to speculate that “if they could get free from the concept of stationary houses, they wouldn’t have to waste energy fighting the sands” (42).

Abe also uses the warring concepts of movement and stability to reveal the man’s dissatisfaction with his career as a teacher. The man seeks the formlessness and nothingness, of flow, but as a teacher, he is moored in the same place with the same curriculum. The man notes that “year after year students tumble along like the waters of a river. They flow away, and only the teacher is left behind, like some deeply buried rock at the bottom of the current” (80). This thematic link to the stasis of the man’s everyday life suggests that his physical struggle to escape the sand pit mirrors his psychological struggle to find freedom from the tedium of his life and career. His students, like the sand, are in constant motion, while he remains stable and stagnant.

blurred text
blurred text
blurred text
blurred text