logo

50 pages 1 hour read

John Henry Newman

The Idea of a University

Nonfiction | Book | Adult | Published in 1873

A modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more.

Themes

The Unity of Truth

One of the predominant ideas in The Idea of the University is that all knowledge has reference to a single thing: that which is true. Newman writes, “All knowledge forms one whole, because its subject-matter is one” (38). There is no place for relativism in Newman’s conception of reality; truth is absolute. Everything that is known must relate to some part of this unity of truth, whether natural or supernatural, and thus all knowledge is conjoined by reason of its singular object:

Truth is the object of Knowledge of whatever kind […]. All that exists, as contemplated by the human mind, forms one large system or complex fact, and this of course resolves itself into an indefinite number of particular facts, which, as being portions of a whole, have countless relations of every kind one towards another. […] And, as all taken together form one integral subject for contemplation, so there are no natural or real limits between part and part; one is ever running into another; all, as viewed by the mind, are combined together, and possess a correlative character one with another, from the internal mysteries of the Divine Essence down to our own sensations and consciousness […] (33-34).

This unity of truth and knowledge has direct implications for Newman’s educational theory. In the first place, Newman regards an intentional fragmentation of truth as problematic. While it is accepted that universities will divide the study of truth into different branches so that a higher level of expertise can be generated in each field, universities must also ensure that all branches of knowledge are represented. Since they all have bearing on one another, removing one will negatively impact students’ ability to perceive the whole: “The systematic omission of any one science from the catalogue prejudices the accuracy and completeness of our knowledge altogether” (39). This is particularly true for theology, which concerns ultimate causes and so has a significant bearing on every field of knowledge.

In addition, Newman believes that the unity of truth should dictate the shape of educational practice. The goal of education is not simply the acquisition of information but the mastery of the whole shape of knowledge: “[…] the power of viewing many things at once as one whole, of referring them severally to their true place in the universal system, of understanding their respective values, and determining their mutual dependence” (103). A student may gain expertise in a single area, but it should be framed and bounded by a broad understanding of all the fields of knowledge and how they fit together. Otherwise, students (and other academics) will be tempted to over-extend the principles of their own limited field of expertise to try to understand other fields, and the misapplication of those principles will result in a warped view of the whole. The aim is to inculcate a fully orbed sense of the whole, such that a student can take new knowledge and contextualize it within the overarching structure. A student should undergo a process of mental formation in which the unity of their understanding reflects the unity of knowledge.

Education as Intellectual Formation

Newman conceives of a university education—or, as he sometimes calls it, a liberal education—as a process of intellectual formation that trains the mind to make use of knowledge rightly and that transforms one’s whole perspective on life. It differs from the reception of information or even the mastery of skills. The memorization of facts may form a part of education, but such practices are not the whole. While Newman concedes a place for learning useful skills, such as in trade schools or under a faculty of law or medicine, he believes that a university education aims for something higher than preparation for a career; it is a program that aspires to perfect the intellectual nature. In the same way that health is the perfection of the body and virtue the perfection of the moral nature, a university education aims to perfect the intellectual nature: “It educates the intellect to reason well in all matters, to reach out toward truth, and to grasp it” (95).

The theoretical basis of this program of intellectual formation is rooted in the unity of truth. To gain what Newman calls “intellectual culture” in one’s mind and perspective, one must gain a familiarity with the many branches of knowledge and their interrelations. This idea of the interconnectedness of knowledge applies not only to the reality of truth, but to the very structure and operations of the human mind: “So much do ideas act, not as solitary units, but by grouping and combination; and so clearly do all the things that fall within the proper province of the same faculty of the mind, intertwine with and support each other” (131).

This formation is achieved by placing a student in the context of university life, where the complex enriching atmosphere—of being amid diverse departments of learning, and of sharing common life with fellow students from many different walks of life—raises the mind beyond its former presuppositions. Intellectual formation also comes through the traditional practices of classical education: studying ancient literary classics, learning Greek and Latin, and undergoing the participatory learning models of both lectures and tutoring. The result, if pursued faithfully, is a cultivated mental perspective that takes new knowledge and applies to it reason and discernment. The student will also be able to consider the challenges of everyday life within the context of a broader understanding of how things work and to pass along their resultant patience, candor, wisdom, and insight for the benefit of others. “A University training,” writes Newman, “is the great ordinary means to a great but ordinary end; it aims at raising the intellectual tone of society [and] at cultivating the public mind” (134). Ultimately, Newman sees university education as useful both for the individual student and for the overall health of all society.

The Relations Between Religion and Science

One of the main tensions that Newman addresses throughout his book is the relationship between religion and science. There was a rising sense in British society in the mid-1800s that religion and science were opposed to one another. The Roman Catholic Church had already earned a reputation as a poor arbiter of that debate in the 17th century, as a result of some Catholic scholars’ repudiation of Galileo in preference for a faulty astronomical model that was not even properly rooted in their own theology. By the 19th century, many other assumptions of traditional Christian teaching were being questioned. Geologists were arguing for a far longer timespan of terrestrial history than had been assumed from conventional interpretations of biblical texts, and by the time Newman edited The Idea of a University into its final structure for the 1873 edition, the theories of Charles Darwin had been sending shockwaves through academic circles for over a decade. At the same time, the multiplication of religious opinions in the wake of the Protestant Reformation had slowly eroded European confidence in the religious doctrine. More and more, scholars regarded theology as a study of subjective opinions. In response, devoted believers in both the Catholic and Protestant churches grew more suspicious of scientific discourse and rationale.

Newman addressed this rising antagonism in several ways. First, he denied that religion and science have significant grounds for criticizing one another. Religion concerns supernatural reality and ultimate causes, which science does not and cannot study, as such matters are beyond empirical scrutiny. Likewise, while science concerns the physical reality that lies open to immediate experimentation, religion teaches nothing of empirical explanations of natural phenomena beyond those phenomena’s ultimate causation by God. The two circles of knowledge intersect, Newman says, but only insofar as to draw inferences from one to the other: “A person who has the fullest knowledge of one of these worlds, may be nevertheless, on the whole, as ignorant as the rest of mankind, as unequal to form a judgment, of the facts and truths of the other” (323).

Second, Newman observed that some of the perceived antagonism results from different methods of reasoning: “The elementary methods of reasoning and inquiring used in Theology and Physics are contrary the one to the other; each of them has a method of its own; and in this, I think, has lain the point of controversy between the two schools” (331). Theology derives from the starting premises given by divine revelation and operates by logical deduction from those premises, reasoning to the doctrines that follow. Science, on the other hand, begins with no such premises; it starts with observation and proceeds by inductive reasoning from the results of its experiments. Both methods are appropriate for their fields. If there is indeed a God who has revealed himself in intelligible ways, then deductive reasoning based on God’s revelations is the only appropriate method of theological study. So also for science: It would be inappropriate to begin with premises where none exist, so one must start with observation and work upward. The difficulty, however, is that the mental habits inculcated by each methodology tend to make one suspicious of the other, more unfamiliar methodology. If a scholar spends their whole life using one set of processes for discerning truth, they would naturally be skeptical of the conclusions reached through an entirely different set of processes. The antagonism in this case is merely apparent, and not real.

Newman’s solution to this perceived antagonism is twofold. First, he believes that the practice of uniting these often-clashing branches of knowledge in a single university will achieve some balance between them: If separated, each branch will tend to ignore the other, but when forced to work together in a university, their harmonies may emerge. Second, he advises patience to his Catholic audience. If they are convinced of the truth of Catholic dogma, then “[nothing] can be discovered by any other scientific method, which can contradict the dogmas of [their] religion” (351). It may turn out, as in the case of Copernican astronomy, that the prevailing Catholic opinions (which were not dogmatically defined) were based on inferior interpretations of biblical revelation. In that circumstance, the overall cause of truth was served, and both science and religion benefited from undergoing a corrective process. Science continually revises its own conclusions upon finding better evidence, and that evidence may serve the cause of religious truth as well as scientific truth. Therefore, patience and a respect for intellectual freedom are the primary virtues for navigating such disputes. Newman ultimately sees the antagonism between science and religion as, at best, a mirage—and, at worst, a case of both branches of knowledge overstepping their bounds. The answer, as throughout The Idea of a University, is to cultivate the sort of intellectual formation that can judge any such disputes with discernment, humility, and clarity of thought.

blurred text
blurred text
blurred text
blurred text