50 pages • 1 hour read
Émile DurkheimA modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more.
With Book 3, Durkheim moves from his assessment of beliefs and focuses more directly on rites and rituals. The most basic forms of religious ritual are those which underscore and establish the division between the sacred and the profane. These rituals come in the form of interdictions or taboos, foremost among which are interdictions of contact, by which the sacred and profane must be kept separate. Thus religious acts are differentiated in time and type from ordinary daily activities; fasting takes on a sacred force because it is the interdiction of an ordinary (and thus profane) act, that of eating. This also leads to the creation of religious calendars, of feast-days and fast-days as differentiated from ordinary time, because time devoted to religious ideas ought not to overlap with time given to ordinary activities; such is the nature of religion’s fundamental separation of sacred and profane. These interdicts and abstentions, though often seen as negative, serve toward a practical effect—by introducing a break from the world of the profane, they allow the person to enter into the world of the sacred. Thus asceticism—often criticized as a negative aspect of religion despite its appearance in many different religious traditions around the world—emerges by contrast as an essential and productive feature of human religion.
The system of interdicts is partly in place to guard against what Durkheim calls the contagiousness of the sacred, as seen in many different religious traditions. “[Religious forces’] intensity incites them to this spreading” (363). Anything drawn into contact with the sacred comes under its power and influence, and thus any profanation is also a consecration, albeit a potentially dangerous one, as the powers of the sacred force are exerted over an object or area which represents the opposing world of the profane. Since sacredness exerts itself like a force—not unlike physical forces like electricity, in Durkheim’s view—it is natural that its compelling emotional power can be extended and experienced in spillover events into profane activities when they come into contact with sacred objects or events. The sacred power is so significant, however, that profane activities (like daily acts of working or eating) are overcome, redefined, or made impossible by contact with it, and thus interdicts serve to protect both the sacred from contamination and the profane from an overpowering contact which would strip it of its own meaning and purpose. Durkheim believes that the interplay of the principles of the sacred and profane in society, far from promoting confusion, opened up new possibilities for human thought and conception, opening the way to logic, philosophy, and science.
Having dealt with asceticism and the interdicts meant to guard against contagion and crossover between the sacred and profane (the negative cult), Durkheim now turns his attention to those features of religion which constitute intentionally sacred acts (the positive cult). Based on a survey of practices in Aboriginal Australian religions, Durkheim undertakes an analysis of the idea of sacrifice, which usually includes the notion of a meal in which the worshipers themselves share, thus becoming participants in the sacrifice. This insight is crucial to Durkheim’s view of sacrifice, regarding it not as offering worship to a deity, but as reaffirming the social bonds which lie at the base of totemic sacredness: “Sacrifice was not founded to create a bond of artificial kinship between a man and his gods, but to maintain and renew the natural kinship which primitively united them” (381).
Sacrifice is characterized by both communion and oblation, consuming sacred food and presenting it as an offering at the same time, and this double nature of giving and receiving also characterizes the nature of religious ritual as a social event. People give their time, presence, and resources for such rituals, and receive as participants not only material substances like food, but a renewal of the vital spiritual dynamic which underlies the social nature of religion: “The real reason for the existence of the cults, even of those which are the most materialistic in appearance, is not to be sought in the acts which they prescribe, but in the internal and moral regeneration which these acts aid in bringing about” (388). The “god” of such rituals—which Durkheim contends is society itself—depends on its worshipers as much its worshipers depend on it, because its existence derives from them, and their morality, language, and art derive from it. This cyclic refreshment of both the worshipers and their god (that is, society itself) is necessarily undertaken in rituals that recur periodically, so that the system can continue operating for the good of all.
Beyond the sacrifice, another positive-cult ritual which is common in Aboriginal Australian societies is the imitative rite, in which people act out the features, attitudes, or life cycle of a totemic animal. The apparent meaning of the rite is to promote fertility in that species and ensure its ongoing existence, following principles of contact and imitation which allow the performers to believe they are directly affecting the animal’s life. Since these rituals are aimed at promoting the continuation of natural cycles which tend to recur on their own, the participants often feel rewarded at seeing the hoped-for results come to pass. When the rituals fail, the participants still have the social benefits of the religious gathering, which have encouraged and refreshed them to such a degree that they cannot conceive of ever abandoning the ritual, regardless of its efficacy. Such rituals promote a conception of the laws of causality which, even if misdirected, allows human thought to develop a philosophy of logic. Durkheim notes that the Aboriginal Australian’s attitude toward his beliefs and their potential falsification is not radically different from those of other religious traditions, nor even of the attitude of a scientist toward their favorite hypothesis. It is the logic of causality inherent in these sympathetic rites which also undergirds the traditional practice of magic in many Indigenous societies, and thus Durkheim believes that magic is derived from religion, not vice versa.
Such rituals and their inherent observation of the laws of causality also inclined the human mind to consider the possibility of force, another key philosophical idea. Durkheim sees in the original notion of force both a moral and personal aspect, and so asserts that it shows its inherently social genesis. Force is also bound up with the idea of power and grades of hierarchy and subordination, which again reveals a social context: “So everything tends to prove that the first powers of which the human mind had any idea were those which societies have established in organizing themselves: it is in their image that the powers of the physical world have been conceived” (409). The simple and categorical nature of these causal conceptions, Durkheim believes, could only have arisen as the product of collective thought and imposed thence on the individual mind.
Durkheim begins his analysis of the next set of positive rites by restating one of his premises regarding Aboriginal Australian ritual: namely, that its meaning is not the one assigned to it by its practitioners, but that it actually exists “to remake individuals and groups morally” (414). He affirms this by pointing out that other rituals, such as those that commemorate long-gone heroes or events, more clearly stand for this purpose. As people are reminded of the great acts of the past, they are grounded in their confidence and inspired by a renewed sense of identity and wholeness. “So we have here a whole group of ceremonies whose sole purpose is to awaken certain ideas and sentiments […]. This is still another proof that the psychical state in which the assembled group happens to be constitutes the only solid and stable basis of what we may call the ritual mentality” (423).
While Durkheim at first denies any useful purpose to these rituals beyond the creation of this mental state, he nonetheless notes that one of the features of religion is to give scope to art, creativity, leisure, and play by the reinvigoration of these moral forces, and this fruitfulness is readily seen in such rituals. Many religious rituals in other traditions have a similar ambiguity—while aimed at a particular function, they also include scope for many other positive effects and can even be adapted for a wide range of different functions (Durkheim notes, for example, that the Catholic mass serves both for weddings and funerals, in addition to its place in weekly worship). Imitative and commemorative rites, Durkheim posits, might be the original forms of religious ritual, as they seem so adaptable and so fruitful for the attainment of many different social goods.
A final category of rituals is what Durkheim calls piacular rites—using a term usually associated with the expiation of sin to denote religious gatherings which respond to sorrow or tragedy. After a survey of Aboriginal Australian rituals for mourning and funerary rites, Durkheim observes that while the rituals include outward shows of sorrow like wailing and weeping, in many cases these are performed as duties of the ritual, not necessarily as an authentic display of the participants’ own emotions. Even though the emotions are different in mourning than in other rites, their social effect remains: “[Mourning], too, is made up out of collective ceremonies which produce a state of effervescence among those who take part in them. The sentiments aroused are different; but the arousal is the same” (445). The social context of mourning helps meet the need for which it occurs; the sense of loss is met with a reminder of social solidarity among those who remain. Other piacular rites, such as ceremonies to respond to a natural disaster or an insufficient harvest, serve the same positive social ends.
The presence of piacular rites also serves to highlight a duality in the idea of sacredness as it appears in many Indigenous societies. While there are beneficent religious forces, such as the totemic principle itself, there are also evil and impure powers, believed to bring death and suffering. These two forces are in opposition to each other, but each retains a sense of the power of its sacred identity, as distinct from the profane. These evil or impure forces are, like the others, representations of social forces, such that when society suffers, it imposes the duty of suffering on its members through their participation in piacular rites. “These beings are nothing other than collective states objectified; they are society itself seen under one of its aspects” (459). The variations in social life, both good and bad, lead to the duality observed in religious thought, with some spiritual forces portrayed as beneficent and others as evil.
Having completed his assessment of Aboriginal Australian religion, Durkheim makes the case that the elemental features of that religion should be considered instructive for our understanding of all human religion. “If among certain peoples the ideas of sacredness, the soul and God are to be explained sociologically, it should be presumed scientifically that, in principle, the same explanation is valid for all the peoples among whom these same ideas are found with the same essential characteristics” (463). Religions recur across all human societies because they are effective vehicles of social identity and social goods; a religious participant feels an infusion of inner strength through the rituals and finds new empowerment for facing the trials of life. Not only is religion an effective vehicle of social good for the individual, but it is, in Durkheim’s view, the root cause of many of the most important developments in human civilization. “In summing up, then, it may be said that nearly all the great social institutions have been born in religion. […] If religion has given birth to all that is essential in society, it is because the idea of society is the soul of religion” (466). Religion is a reflection of society itself, transmuted into an active form in which it can shape and inspire its members.
Durkheim views his own historical moment as representing the withering of existing religious traditions (such as the decline of traditional Christian attachments in early 20th-century Europe), but he does not view an age of irreligion as a likely future for humanity. Rather, because of its nature as an essential expression of social values and social force, some form of religion will continue to arise as a dominant feature of human experience. Science will not eclipse religion, since religion is a feature of human reality itself; science and religion serve different functions and both should be expected to continue their course. Religion is one of the main vehicles by which society has developed the concepts which lead to further philosophical and logical avenues of thought. Durkheim goes so far as to put society’s effect on the individual in quasi-religious terms himself: “[…] we must say that society is not at all the illogical or a-logical, incoherent and fantastic being which it has too often been considered. On the contrary, the collective consciousness is the highest form of the psychic life, since it is the consciousness of the consciousnesses” (492). Society is not simply a structure put in place by humans, but an active set of forces which operates independently of any individual control; an epiphenomenon of human consciousness which exists above the individual and in which the individual comes to perceive and conceptualize the features of their own life.
Book 3 of The Elementary Forms of the Religious Life focuses on the rituals of totemic religion, in contrast to Book 2’s focus on totemic belief systems. As such, Durkheim’s thematic focus on The Function of Religious Rituals in Society finds its fullest treatment here. By examining possible meanings behind negative, positive, and piacular rites, Durkheim works them into his argument for a social origin of religion. His main interpretation of negative rites is that they serve to underscore the fundamental religious division between the sacred and profane, while the positive and piacular rites, due to their strongly communal nature, exist to offer renewed experiences of the fundamental social forces on which the religious system is based.
It should be noted yet again that Durkheim’s reconstruction of the meaning of these rituals is necessarily speculative; he is suggesting a possible meaning beyond what the religion’s own practitioners would admit. This illustrates a certain lack of cultural sensitivity, a common feature even in the cultural anthropology circles of Durkheim’s day. He brushes aside the Aboriginal Australian understandings of their own rituals without even a serious examination. For example, at the beginning of Chapter 4, he writes: “The physical efficaciousness assigned to them by the believer is the product of an interpretation which conceals the essential reason for their existence” (414). Durkheim’s theory is as much the product of an interpretation as theirs is, and one which is offered by a cultural outsider rather than an insider. While more modern treatments of Indigenous religion would not necessarily be obliged to agree with the Aboriginal Australians’ religious interpretation of their rituals, they would accord that interpretation significantly more respect. Such sequences reveal Durkheim’s book to be a product of its own time, in which it was common to diminish an insider perspective in favor of one’s own outsider perspective. It was not until the 1930s and ‘40s that European cultural anthropologists would begin to let indigenous cultures speak on their own terms, without judging or disallowing the concepts they held.
Of all the book’s sections, this final set of chapters leans more toward sociology than anthropology. Especially in his Conclusion, but even amid his analysis of religious rituals, Durkheim gives his attention to broad sociological themes, such as the dynamics of collective conceptualization within a society and the effects of the idea of force on a social system. This shows Durkheim in his natural element, building up the foundations of the discipline of sociology by calling on broad philosophical concepts relating to human society. Most of the book’s exploration of religion and speculation as to its origins could have been written just as easily by an anthropologist as a sociologist, but this final section, which seeks to expand and apply the book’s thesis to all religions and all human societies, establishes the book firmly in the field of sociology.