logo

47 pages 1 hour read

Marcus Aurelius

Meditations

Nonfiction | Book | Adult | Published in 180

A modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more.

Key Figures

Marcus Aurelius

In Meditations, Marcus Aurelius makes only passing reference to his being the emperor of Rome. He once refers to himself as a “ruler” and elsewhere makes cryptic references to his station (19). One notable example is when he cautions himself “not to be Caesarified, or dyed in purple” (51), with the former a reference to those who preceded him in his office (who held the title Caesar), and the latter to the color (purple) reserved for ruling classes. Other passing comments treat his role as one that either presents an obstacle to living the virtues he believes in or an opportunity to manifest his discipline by rejecting its trappings. If he were not famed as the “philosophical emperor,” one could conceivably read Meditations and fail to realize that he served in the highest office of a vast empire.

In part, this may be due to the private nature of his writing. Marcus would hardly need to keep reminding himself that he is the emperor, especially given the intention of his Meditations as a corrective exercise for his own moral improvement. Nevertheless, the inattention he gives to his role is telling of its unimportance to him, which accords with his overall goal to divest things in the material world of their fanciful embellishments and boil them down to their essentials. For him, this seems in part to mean divesting himself of the vanity and entitlement that might be expected of a man in his office.

A question that has been debated about Marcus is, to what extent did he adhere to his own philosophical ideals? To answer this, it is helpful to recall how Stoics frame the concept of freedom and how they did not. Political and legal rights were not their locus of concern; rather, freedom meant liberty from committing moral errors and submitting to impulses. In practice, Stoicism was concerned with how individuals thought about and behaved in their own lives, in whatever role they held in society. Whether one was the emperor or an enslaved member of his household, from a Stoic perspective, both are “free” to exercise their reason and liberate themselves from pain and harm by choosing how they frame their reality. Indeed, a criticism of Stoicism has been that it does not present a framework that encourages interrogation of political and social conditions.

Marcus evokes characteristically Stoic expressions of what it means to be enslaved in several places in his Meditations. In Book 4, he entreats himself to commit “all of his being to the gods” and in this way never to make himself “tyrant or slave to any man” (29). In Book 8, he describes emperors as “slaves to all their ambitions” (72). Later in the same book, he notes that a slave who escapes from his master becomes a “fugitive,” then compares resisting submission to pain or anger as “fugitive” action, in that it refuses to acknowledge the natural order. Across his Meditations, Marcus shows himself struggling to take control of his thoughts, to regulate his actions accordingly, and to seek to align himself with the workings of the divine. In a Stoic sense, he can be said to have strived to live in accordance with his ideals, with respect to what he expected of and owed to himself and what he expected of and owed to his fellow humans and the divine.

Epictetus

A Stoic philosopher whose works Marcus quotes in the Meditations and whom he credits as a strong influence on his own philosophical development was Epictetus. A compilation of his teachings has appeared as Discourses, The Art of Living, and On Human Freedom, in various English translations. A preface to the work suggests that they were not the writings of Epictetus himself and could perhaps be notes assembled by students who attended his lectures. As they are composed in Koine Greek, they have been accepted as expressing his own work.

Epictetus was born at some point in the 50s in the Greek city of Hierapolis in Asia Minor. Whether he was born enslaved or became so later is not clear, but he apparently lived as an enslaved member of the household of one of Roman Emperor Nero’s administrators. He is believed to have studied under Rufus, a Stoic philosopher and Roman senator and, after being freed, to have established his own school of philosophy at Nicopolis in Greece, where he remained until his death in 135.

Epictetus’s philosophy, as expressed in the Discourses, hinges on his belief that to be human is to be rational and moral. Human rationality is nested within a rational universe designed by the divine (Zeus or the gods, for Epictetus). Humans have been endowed with free will (some translators have used the term “volition”), meaning the freedom to choose how to act. Thus, emotions are understood to be shaped by one’s beliefs rather than imposed from external circumstances. Care for self and care for others are intertwined, and the proper stance to take towards other is philanthropic (literally, “love of humanity”). His teaching method combined textual study with exercises for living that were meant to cultivate the proper practices and attitudes that moved one along their path toward virtue.

Plato’s Socrates

Plato and his Socrates predate Stoicism but remained influential. The character of Socrates as characterized by Plato in his dialogues—the primary means through which Marcus would have encountered him, since Socrates left no writing of his own behind—appears in Meditations as an example of virtuous behavior. In the works of Plato, Socrates can be understood as the embodiment of philosophy, elevating him to the status of a heroic figure, a superhuman force whose power can be called upon in a protective capacity.

He is mentioned several times in Meditations, most memorably in Book 7, when Marcus lauds him for his “glorious death,” exemplary ability to argue against sophists, endurance “in spending a whole night out in the frost,” and bravery in “refusing the order to arrest Leon of Salamis” (68). The list draws on aspects of Socrates’s life that are recounted in Plato’s various dialogues. After being condemned to death for allegedly corrupting the youth of Athens in 399 BC, Socrates famously chose to submit to the legal order rather than violate the law by fleeing into exile. During his war service, Socrates was famed for being calm and steadfast under harrowing conditions, including extreme cold and disorderly retreat. His refusal to arrest Leon of Salamis refers to an unjust order that Socrates refused to enforce.

Having presented what appears to be evidence of Socrates’s virtuous behavior, Marcus then counters that the nature of his soul is what must be examined: whether he was content “with a life of justice shown to men and piety to the gods; neither condemning all vice wholesale nor yet toadying to anyone’s ignorance; not regarding anything allotted to him by the Whole as misplaced in him or a crushing burden to endure; not lending his mind to share the poor passions of the flesh” (68). Marcus’s description of Socrates resonates with his earlier description of the characteristics of a good man in Book 3: one who gives all his attention to his own fate as apportioned by the Whole.

blurred text
blurred text
blurred text
blurred text