55 pages • 1 hour read
Thomas PikettyA modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more.
Summary
Chapter Summaries & Analyses
Key Figures
Themes
Index of Terms
Important Quotes
Essay Topics
Tools
To understand the inequality and accumulation of wealth, Piketty looks at the roles of inheritance and savings in capital formation. His broad conclusion is that “the past tends to devour the future” (477). In other words, wealth from inheritance will always tend to predominate, and grow more quickly, than savings possible in an individual’s lifetime from work. This was true to an even greater extent historically. In the 19th century, increasing slightly between 1800 and 1910, the annual inheritance flow as a proportion of national income stood at between twenty and twenty-five percent. After the second world war, however, and by 1950-1960 the same figure was barely more than four to five percent in France. This led to “the idea that the age of inheritance was over” (480). Yet, like wealth, inheritance flow started to increase in the 1970s and 80s, reaching around half of what it had been between 1880 and 1910.
Piketty assesses the argument that as life expectancy increases the importance of inheritance in society diminishes. He acknowledges that the average age of inheritance has increased from around thirty in the 19th century to fifty in the 21st century. However, he claims, this delay is compensated for the fact that inheritances therefore tend to be larger, having accumulated over a longer period. It is also compensated for by a greater number of gifts given by parents to children in their lifetimes. By 2010, Piketty argues, inheritance had come to represent about a quarter of total lifetime resources for those born in 1970s cohorts. Further, he predicts that for cohorts born in the 21st century, inheritance could represent as much as a third or four tenths of lifetime resources. It would then have surpassed its quantitative significance in the 19th century.
Nevertheless, there are some differences between the 19th or earlier 20th century and the present. First, the distribution of inherited wealth has changed, so that there are now fewer huge fortunes but more large and middling ones. This, combined with a later age of inheritance, means that, in contrast to the 19th century, the rich now are more likely to acquire a skill and work as well as deriving an income from inheritance. We have moved to a society of “petit rentiers”, and one where income and wealth inequality are mixed in a more complex fashion.
Still, this does not necessarily mean that society overall is more meritocratic. This is because access to higher incomes and the educations necessary to earn them are still largely determined by birth. Income disparities tend to translate themselves across generations almost as consistently as inherited wealth. Further, the inequalities in inheritance and wealth relative to labour income are still huge. For example, in France between 2010 and 2020 around one sixth of each cohort receive an inheritance at some point greater than the bottom half of the population for wealth will receive in a lifetime.
This chapter looks at global wealth inequality on an international level. As such, it asks whether the forces of financial globalization will lead to even greater world-wide wealth inequalities. To do this Piketty examines whether individual fortunes worldwide have increased and if inequalities between countries are growing.
Before tackling these questions directly, Piketty introduces a further theoretical caveat regarding the nature of wealth, namely that there are economies of scale when it comes to the return on capital. This is for two reasons. First, those with a greater fortune are more easily able to employ financial intermediaries, such as wealth management consultants and financial advisers. Second, it is easier for those with large amounts of capital to take risks and be patient. In addition, the wealthier need use less of their capital to live and can employ creative accounting to avoid tax. If the average return on capital is four percent, the wealthy could get a six or seven percent return, whereas smaller investors get only two or three percent. This means that wealth tends to concentrate, if unchecked, to extreme levels.
Returning to global wealth, reports indicate that the global distribution of wealth is even more unequal than the distributions of wealth within nations. As Piketty explains, “The top thousandth seems to own nearly twenty percent of total global wealth today, the top centile about fifty percent, and the top decile somewhere between eighty and ninety percent” (554). In contrast, the bottom fifty percent own less than five percent of global wealth. Further, he estimates that the sovereign wealth funds (the government invested wealth) of petroleum producing nations could own ten to twenty percent of global wealth by 2030-2040. This could present serious problems for democracy because such funds could come to own substantial industry, resources, and real estate in other nations, obliging the latter to pay “rent” to non-nationals, thereby increasing their funds. Thus, sovereign wealth funds on a large scale present as much of a problem for the equitable distribution of wealth as huge and growing individual fortunes.
As discussed, extreme inequalities in income from labour that have arisen since the 1980s are hard to justify meritocratically. What about inequalities of wealth? As Piketty notes, “the concentration of wealth remains high” (476). It’s not as high as it was in the 1800s, but it is growing. As he says, “The top thousandth seems to own nearly twenty percent of total global wealth today, the top centile about fifty percent, and the top decile somewhere between eighty and ninety percent” (554). Meanwhile, the bottom fifty percent of the world still owns nothing. At the same time, there is now a middle class that own between twenty-five and thirty percent of wealth which did not exist in the 19th century. Perhaps, combined with the emergence of self-made millionaires like Oprah Winfrey and Steve Jobs, wealth itself has become more meritocratic. Perhaps, despite the inequalities, it is no longer quite the closed shop that it was for Rastignac in Pere Goriot.
But to assess whether this is true and to judge the meritocratic status of contemporary wealth, it is necessary first to stress that wealth inequality is not, in principle, an automatically bad thing. If one chooses to save or invest a portion of one’s income, one generates wealth. Further, if this capital yields a return, then this can be seen as compensation for the willingness to delay consumption. The problem, some might argue, comes when that saved wealth turns into inheritance. For, contra rational choice economic models, people do not just save to ensure funds for retirement, or higher future consumption. They also save, as Piketty says, “to amass or perpetuate a family fortune” (504), or to have the prestige of accumulated wealth.
In these latter cases, some of the next generation arbitrarily gain a sum of unearned, unsaved wealth, something which starts to give them an income and amasses further wealth. Given the capacity of larger fortunes to grow quicker, this can, over a few generations, generate large and self-perpetuating wealth disparities. And these will have nothing to do with savings choices or individual merit. Indeed, this is what is currently being seen in the West. The shocks of world war, decolonization, and post-war government nationalisations, destroyed much of the inherited wealth existing in Europe and the US. But this has started to recover. For example, in France, from inheritance constituting just five percent of national income between 1910 and 1950, this figure leapt to fifteen percent in 2010. Indeed, it may well reach the historic highs of twenty five percent, achieved at the start of the 20th century, in the years and decades to come.
All of which may suggest a troubling, though intuitively obvious, point about wealth. Namely, the longer it is allowed to accumulate, in the absence of extrinsic shocks, on a societal level both the less meritocratic and more unequally distributed it becomes. The arbitrariness of the past, of one’s parents’ and grandparents’ wealth, comes to determine one’s chances in the present. Now, of course, it can be argued that inheritance in middle-class families does follow the extremes of large, dynastic fortunes. Gifts of a few thousand euros or inheritances of tens or hundreds of thousands from parental estate later in life this may help make life more comfortable or secure, but they won’t replace earned income.
Yet, issues still arise. First, as Piketty points out, despite its relatively modest size, such inheritances and gifts “can have a major impact in deciding who will own property and who will not, at what age, and how extensive that property will be” (481). In other words, any inheritance not only seriously affects standards of living, it also helps to re-enforce and perpetuate existing class distinctions. This is especially true given the fluid relation between wealth and income. Inherited wealth may allow one to send one’s children to college, or to private schools, thus allowing them a higher income. Conversely, those whose parents have no wealth are more likely to be stuck in an intergenerational cycle of low income and zero wealth.
In summary, then, the emergence of a middle class has doubtless spread the benefits of wealth more widely. It has also provided a broader social base, and support, for the ideals of property ownership and capital accumulation. Yet it has not fundamentally obviated the essentially unmeritocratic character of wealth or inheritance. These remain, albeit in more complex and stratified forms than in the 19th century, and with more intertwined relations with high labour incomes. Nor will the middle class provide a bulwark against ever deepening and unmeritocratic inequality in the coming century. That is, it will not provide a defense against the development of what Piketty calls “the worst of two worlds,” a world of “both very large inequality of inherited wealth and very high wage inequality justified in terms of merit and productivity” (528).
Business & Economics
View Collection
Challenging Authority
View Collection
Community
View Collection
Equality
View Collection
Philosophy, Logic, & Ethics
View Collection
Politics & Government
View Collection
Power
View Collection
Required Reading Lists
View Collection
Sociology
View Collection
SuperSummary Staff Picks
View Collection