logo

62 pages 2 hours read

Kathryn Schulz

Being Wrong: Adventures in the Margin of Error

Nonfiction | Book | Adult | Published in 2010

A modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more.

Part 1, Chapters 1-2Chapter Summaries & Analyses

Part 1: “The Idea of Error”

Part 1, Chapter 1 Summary: “Wrongology”

Chapter 1 opens by exploring the relatable experience of making a mistake, which evokes feelings like embarrassment and stirs many negative associations like “stupidity,” “indolence,” “psychopathology,” and “moral degeneracy.” However, the author asserts that this “meta-mistake” (5)—being wrong about what it means to be wrong—is our biggest error. This book intends to reveal how, instead, error is vital to human cognition, inseparable from humane qualities such as optimism, and a crucial part of learning and growth.

The author explains that although fallibility is inextricable from the human experience, when we do err, we often deny it, ignore it, or blame someone else. Schulz insists that we, as a culture, have not mastered the ability to say, “I was wrong” (7), despite how frequent and perpetual our mistakes. Here, the author introduces the Pessimistic Meta-Induction from the History of Science, which states that most past scientific theories were eventually discredited, so we must assume that today’s theories will also prove wrong. This principle is broad and extends to all theories, including our own beliefs about the world, which we often replace with new beliefs that will themselves come to be replaced.

Philosophers such as John Locke and Martin Heidegger established their own philosophies of error, as many have done through history. Locke believed error arises from the gap between the artifice of our words and the reality of what they signify. Heidegger believed error stems from our inability to view reality as a whole; we are bound by time and space.

Attempts to define wrongness, Schulz says, have given rise to the field of error studies, which categorizes various errors with the goal of limiting the chances and impacts of future mistakes. However, the author distinguishes herself from defining error thus, choosing instead to focus on the subjective experience of being wrong and how to use it to rethink our relationships with others, ourselves, and the world.

Regarding this experience of error, the author states that “error-blindness” means that our misconceptions are, by definition, invisible to us. “Error-blindness” helps to explain why we are so surprised by our own mistakes. A paradox lies in the experience of being wrong in that, once we know we are wrong, we stop believing the falsehood and are thus no longer wrong. Schulz contends that we are also quicker to forget our mistakes than to remember them. Additionally, rather than sitting with our simple state of “wrongness,” we file errors away as learning experiences, embarrassing moments, and things we used to believe.

Given our “error-blindness,” quickness to forget our mistakes, and tendency to replace old beliefs, the author states that it is no surprise that we have so much difficulty accepting that error is a part of who we are. In fact, acknowledging our errors means “we suddenly find ourselves at odds with ourselves” (21), provoking a kind of existential identity crisis. This experience, however, presents an opportunity to see things—including ourselves—in a different light.

Part 1, Chapter 2 Summary: “Two Models of Wrongness”

Chapter 2 begins by introducing the pessimistic model of error, which views error as perilous and distasteful, evoking feelings of humiliation. However, says Schulz, this model is incomplete because it acknowledges that wrongness is disagreeable, but it does not explain why. By contrast, the optimistic model of error does not associate error with shamefulness, instead allowing feelings such as surprise, hilarity, and delight to occur in the face of mistakes.

The author uses the perspective of 19th-century philosopher William James to illustrate the optimistic model or error, and she uses that of medieval monk Thomas Aquinas to illustrate the pessimistic model. James doubted whether erring could truly be abnormal and abhorrent if we continuously do it, but Aquinas saw erring as “a perversion of the prescribed order of things” (28). More than telling us about wrongness, this debate, says Schulz, demonstrates more who we think we are and what kind of world we think we live in. In Aquinas’s view, the mind is a vehicle for truth, and thus error is a disgraceful perplexity. From this viewpoint, error deserves eradication. James, however, did not see the mind as reflecting true reality; this perspective makes error both acceptable and explainable.

Aquinas’s notion of eradicating error is countered by the principles of the Scientific Revolution and the development of the scientific method, in which observations beget hypotheses that are subjected to experimentation. This method prizes falsification, as hypotheses and theories are defined by their potential to be proven wrong; if a claim is not falsifiable, it is not empirical and therefore not scientific. Error is thus useful. The Scientific Revolution teaches that, instead of error misleading us, it brings us ever closer to the truth. Error is essential to knowledge.

Early 19th-century French mathematician and astronomer Pierre-Simon Laplace developed a theory of the distribution of errors known as the bell curve, which is a means of aggregating various data points to produce an accurate big picture, or generalization. For thinkers of the time, the bell curve represented the ability to contain and curtail error into revealing its opposite—the truth.

The author then turns to the misperception of reality as an instance of error revealing rather than obscuring the truth. Throughout history, many people have enjoyed the false reality of dreams as well as that induced by hallucinogenic substances. The dream-worlds brought on by such altered states present all the indicators of reality—“all the intimacy, intensity, and physicality” (37)—and yet when these states are experienced, “the false and the true are reversed” (37), and the world’s governing rules are altered: The unreal becomes the real. Prolonged changes in our understanding of reality are what we consider to be “insanity” (38), and if “madness is radical wrongness, being wrong is minor madness” (39). Nevertheless, Schulz asserts, societies throughout history have believed that “insanity” can reveal things as they truly are. In the Western literary tradition, for example, the archetypal figures of “the fools […] and the madmen” (39) often speak the greatest truths. This notion that error yields insight—that it is vital to the process of creation and invention—is a key insight of the optimistic model of wrongness.

Thus, under the pessimistic model, errors obscure the truth, lead us astray, and should be eliminated. Under the optimistic model, errors expose the truth, are inevitable, and are part of the human condition.

Part 1, Chapters 1-2 Analysis

These early chapters’ ideas are a necessary preface to Being Wrong because they situate Schulz’s work in a long philosophical, scientific, literary tradition. The author reviews historical attempts to define and delineate wrongness, showing how centuries-long Western thought has sought an accurate definition of error (Locke and Heidegger exemplify such thinkers). The field of error studies is a modern-day means of categorizing wrongness, and the Pessimistic Meta-Induction from the History of Science is a major scientific and philosophical theory of error. However, Schulz details these theories not only to contextualize her own study but to contrast herself against the traditional discourse: Rather than trying to neatly define the multifaceted complexity of human error, the author will focus on how we feel and think about being wrong. This distinct approach is crucial to her ultimate intention; rather than theoretical clarity, she seeks actual transformation in individual lives, hoping that we can learn to view our fallibility as a path toward insight into others, ourselves, and the world around us.

The author’s distinct approach, in this regard, also becomes a theme that emerges in these chapters: how we view and feel about erring—chiefly, our tremendous (and counterproductive) aversion to it, and what that aversion costs us. Although fallibility is intrinsic to humanity, being wrong can evoke a range of unpleasant feelings, primarily shame-based. When we do make a mistake, we often ignore it or react defensively. The author asserts that Western culture has not mastered the ability to admit personal error, due to such distasteful associations with the experience. People will therefore categorize such instances of personal error under the umbrella of “embarrassing moments” and “lessons learned”—but these interpretations of personal error function to mitigate our discomfort, and they prevent us from using our wrongness more constructively. Moreover, we are limited in our very perception of error; humans have a tendency toward “error-blindness,” in which our error exists entirely because we are oblivious to it. This presents a kind of paradox whereby once we know we are wrong, we cease to be wrong, and we thus can never simply sit with being wrong. Our experience of erring—in addition to being distasteful—is highly elusive. Finally, Schulz demonstrates how being wrong causes an internal conflict as we find ourselves at odds with what we thought we knew about ourselves, resulting in a kind of identity crisis. This discomfort is yet another of our negative reactions to the experience of being wrong.

These chapters also present two contrasting models of wrongness. The author includes these models not for the mere sake of contrast, but to illuminate an entire, unexplored paradigm shift. There is the pessimistic model of wrongness and the optimistic model. The pessimistic model is in keeping with our general feelings about being wrong, such as humiliation and defeat. The author argues, however, that this is our “meta-mistake” (5)—we are wrong about what it means to be wrong. On the other hand, the optimistic model of error not only enables us to experience other emotions in the face of mistakes, such as surprise and delight, but it can also help us rethink how we relate to ourselves, others, and the world in general. Furthermore, through this model, we can come to view erring—seeing the world as it is not—as the essence of imagination and creativity. Error is also framed as a springboard for insight in its ability to bring us closer to the truth. Through this perspective, the author sheds a whole new light on the nature of erring, revealing its potential beyond the traditionally dysphoric associations.

blurred text
blurred text
blurred text
blurred text