logo

92 pages 3 hours read

Robert M. Sapolsky

Behave: The Biology of Humans at Our Best and Worst

Nonfiction | Book | Adult | Published in 2017

A modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more.

Background

Normative Ethics: Deontology and Consequentialism

Early on in Behave, Sapolsky eschews the concepts of right and wrong, good and evil, and prosocial and antisocial in favor of two “concepts that truly defy brevity” (20): best and worst. Sapolsky does so because he writes from the perspective that, though science can tell us much about the reasons we behave in one way or another, it cannot tell us if these behaviors are innately good or bad. This depends on context.

The argument that right and wrong depend on context emerges from Sapolsky’s career as a scientist, but it is indebted to an intellectual history primarily outside of science. This is the field of normative ethics, a genre of philosophy that deals with the moral quality of behaviors. The question of what is right and wrong is one of the earliest strains in philosophy, with different arguments throughout the ages generally categorizable into two competing perspectives: deontological ethics and consequentialist ethics.

Deontology, from the Greek δέον (deon): “rule/duty,” and λόγος (logos): “study,” is the idea that morality is and should be bound by inviolable rules. In this framework, the morality of an act is innate to the act itself depending on whether the act breaks a moral rule. For instance, one moral rule is that it is wrong to kill. Therefore, any act of killing is immoral, irrelevant of its context. This concept of morality is expressed early in recorded history in certain doctrinal religious perspectives on morality, such as the Ten Commandments. Within modern philosophy, deontology is largely traced to Immanuel Kant, who believed the highest good is a good in itself, meaning a goodness with intrinsic good quality. Acts are moral in a Kantian framework when they act in duty to the good.

Consequentialism, also referred to as utilitarianism, is the alternative to the deontological idea. It argues acts are morally correct or incorrect not based on the nature of the act but on the act’s consequence, or utility. For instance, it is morally incorrect to kill in murder because its consequence is needless death, but it is morally correct to kill in certain wars because its consequence is protecting your homeland. Early philosophical incarnations of consequentialism include classical Greek philosophy, which saw virtue as based upon living one’s best life (including killing in war). Within modern philosophy, consequentialism is largely associated with Jeremy Bentham, who coined the term.

Sapolsky tangles with these two moral philosophies throughout Behave, constantly landing on the consequentialist perspective. His morally ambiguous description of killing Hitler, which incites the book, or his description of the movement of fingers and their varied consequences at the beginning of Chapter 1 (see Quote 4) express this view. The debate between deontology and utilitarianism is most specifically discussed regarding the trolley problem in Chapter 13. Put into action on this problem, a consequentialist would consider it acceptable to kill one to save five (a net profit of four lives) while a deontologist would be forced to do nothing (killing five through inaction). Sapolsky’s core point in this moment is that the human brain is capable of both, depending on which of its specific structures are activated: “When deontologism and consequentialism contemplate trolleys, the former is about moral intuitions rooted in the vmPFC, amygdala, and insula while the latter is the domain of the dlPFC” (505). What activates these regions? Us, and our choices, based on our environment, and our genetics, and the environment of our genetics, and our culture, and endless other contextual factors. Morality does not just depend on context; it depends on varied interdependent contexts.

Sciences of Animal and Human Behavior: Behaviorism, Ethology, Adaptationism, and Spandrelism

Much, but not all, of the science of human behavior has its correlates in the animal kingdom. This means that studying the dynamics of animal behavior will tell us much about human behavior. Both Behave as a text and Sapolsky as a scientist sit at the intersection of four prominent ways of examining animal behavior and its human correlates. These perspectives can be organized into two pairs.

The first pair, behaviorism and ethology, are two ways of looking at how environments condition behavior in species. Sapolsky talks about these two frameworks for studying animal behavior at length at the beginning of Chapter 3.

Behaviorism is the study of animal behavior through solely observable phenomena. This field proposes that all behavior can be explained via one universal rule: animals are more likely to enact behaviors for which they are rewarded and less likely to enact behaviors they for which they are punished. Therefore, hypothetically any behavior can be made more or less common in any organism based on the methodical application of rewards or punishments, which is a process known as “operant conditioning.” This field emerged in the early 20th century and was most prominently championed by the famous researcher B. F. Skinner. The same rule of operant conditioning, in the behaviorist concept, applies to humans based on the logic of reward and punishment.

Ethology is the intellectual response to behaviorism. Its focus is on the infinite variety of behavior, i.e., its non-universality. Though all species can be driven to or from specific acts via reward and punishment, the repertoire of acts they are capable of depends on the unique demands put on these species within their evolutionary histories. Furthermore, to focus on the fact of observable behavior ignores all the species-specific nuance of behavior that is unseen: the ultrasonic chirping of mice, or the ultraviolent markings on flowers to attract bees. Operant conditioning, though it has its place in shaping potential behaviors, misses out on the much deeper universal: All the different behaviors species are capable of depend on their environmental conditions.

The new universal rule, that behavior depends on conditions of the evolutionary environment, applies to human behavior as well, where it is referred to as adaptationism. Adaptationism is the idea that all human behaviors, including the behaviors we find abhorrent (murder, racism, greed, deceit, etc.) exist because they were adaptive in our evolutionary environment. This leads us to an ethical problem, which is outlined at length at the end of Chapter 10: if all human behavior has adaptive ends, does this excuse immorality via its deeper evolutionary “virtue?” This leads to adaptationism’s own intellectual response, which is the idea of spandrelism. Spandrelism and the accompanying concept of exaptation is the idea that several behavioral traits present in humans did not evolve for any adaptive purpose but are byproducts of other adaptive traits.

As Sapolsky notes on both of these debates and more broadly throughout his book, an ethics of coexistence is key. Any idea that proposes itself as the universal explanation of all behavior will prove itself false because evolution is a tinkerer, working with what lays before it and therefore constantly breaking rules and adding caveats. This does not mean that either behaviorism or adaptationism is completely false either. Each has their place, as do ethology and spandrelism. To devolve into either complete universalism or complete relativism cancels all the nuance science exposes, which are often the most important things.

blurred text
blurred text
blurred text
blurred text